Verb phrase ellipsis

In linguistics, verb phrase ellipsis (VP-ellipsis or VPE) is an elliptical construction in which a non-finite verb phrase has been left out (elided). VP-ellipsis is a well studied kind of ellipsis,[1] although it appears to occur mainly in English.[2]

Contents

Basic traits

Auxiliary licensors

The first thing to acknowledge about VP-ellipsis is that the elided VP must be a non-finite VP; it cannot be a finite VP. Further, the ellipsis must be introduced by an auxiliary verb (be, can, do, don't, could, have, may, might, should, will, won't, would) or by the infinitive particle to. The elided material of VP-ellipsis is indicated using subscripts and a smaller font:

You might do it, but I won't do it.
She won't laugh, but he will laugh.
Susan has been cheating, and Fred has been cheating too.

Attempts at VP-ellipsis that lack an auxiliary verb fail:

*Sam wants to eat, and Fred wants to eat, too. - Star * indicates the sentence is bad.
*Josh likes to sleep late, and Hillary likes to sleep late, too.

Apparent exceptions to this aspect of VP-ellipsis may be instances of null complement anaphora, e.g. ?Bill tried to leave, and Jim tried, too.

Forwards or backwards and downwards or upwards

The examples just produced have the antecedent to the ellipsis preceding the ellipsis, and ellipsis is operating across coordinated clauses, whereby these clauses (since they are coordinated) are equi-level. The following examples illustrate in this area that VP-ellipsis can operate forwards or backwards as well as downwards or upwards:

The people who say they will help never do help. - Forwards and upwards
The people who say they will help never do help. - Backwards and downwards
The people never do help, who say the will help. - Forwards and downwards
*The people never do help, who say the will help. - Backwards and upwards

VP-ellipsis operates forwards when the antecedent to the ellipsis precedes the ellipsis. It operates downwards when the antecedent appears in a clause that is superordinate to the clause containing the ellipsis. Three of the four combinations are acceptable. VP-ellipsis is, however, impossible when it operates both backwards and upwards.

Antecedent-contained ellipsis

An aspect of VP-ellipsis that has been the cause of much theorizing occurs when the ellipsis appears to be contained inside its antecedent.[3] The phenomenon is called antecedent-contained ellipsis (=antecedent-contained deletion). Canonical cases of antecedent-contained ellipsis occur when the ellipsis appears inside a quantified object NP, e.g.

They said everything that we did say. - Antecedent-contained ellipsis
He is thinking the same thing I am thinking. - Antecedent-contained ellipsis

The apparent antecedent to the ellipsis is the VP in italics. The fact that this antecedent VP contains the ellipsis itself means that an infinite regress occurs. An infinite regress is, however, an impossibility, since it would mean that the ellipsis could never acquire full semantic content.

One means of addressing antecedent-contained ellipsis that is pursued in some phrase structure grammars is to assume quantifier raising (QR). Quantifier raising raises the quantified NP to a position where it is no longer contained inside its antecedent VP. An alternative explanation (i.e. an alternative to the QR analysis) pursued in dependency grammars is to assume that the basic unit of syntax is not the constituent, but rather the catena.[4] A catena-based analysis of sentence structure sees the antecedent to the ellipsis as a non-constituent catena. What this means is that no movement mechanism (e.g. no QR) is needed to account for the fact that an infinite regress is an impossibility. The antecedent to the ellipsis is a catena that does not in any sense contain the ellipsis.

Argument-contained ellipsis

A phenomenon that overlaps to an extent with antecedent-contained ellipsis is argument-contained ellipsis.[5] Canonical cases of argument-contained ellipsis have the VP-ellipsis appearing inside the subject argument (as opposed to inside the object argument). The 'forwards/backwards' examples above involve argument-contained ellipsis, and the following examples illustrate the phenomenon further:

The people who wanted to stay did stay.
The people who wanted to stay did stay. - Argument contained ellipsis
The kid that should have studied didn't study.
The kid that should have studied didn't study. - Argument contained ellipsis

The second sentence in each pair is an instance of argument contained ellipsis. The VP-ellipsis appears inside an argument of its antecedent predicate. Note that these cases do not involve antecedent contained ellipsis because the ellipsis appears in the subject argument, which is indisputably outside of the antecedent VP.

The mysterious aspect of argument contained ellipsis concerns the environments in which it is and is not possible, e.g.[6]

*A proof that God exists does exist.
*A proof that God does exist exists. - Failed argument contained ellipsis

Comparing these two sentences with those immediately above, a fundamental question arises: When is argument contained ellipsis possible, and when is it not possible? The situation seems even more convoluted when one examines the following contrast:

The guy who wanted to order the salmon did order the salmon.
They guy who wanted to order the salmon did order the salmon. - Argument contained ellipsis
*The guy who wanted Bill to order the salmon did order the salmon.
*The guy wanted Bill to order the salmon did order the salmon. - Failed argument contained ellipsis

Argument contained ellipsis is possible in the first pair of sentences, but not in the second. These data remain mysterious to the present day, since a satisfactory theoretical account of the contrast is lacking.

Notes

  1. ^ See for instance Hankamer and Sag 1976, Hardt 1993, and Johnson 2001.
  2. ^ But see Goldberg 2005 for a sustained argument that verb phrase ellipsis is found in certain verb-raising languages as well.
  3. ^ See for example Kennedy 1997 and Wilder 2003.
  4. ^ See for instance Osborne and Groß 2012.
  5. ^ See Kennedy 1994.
  6. ^ The examples are from Wasow 1972.

References

See also